Book III. Of the Principles of the Three Kinds of Government
1. Difference between the Nature and Principle of Government. Having examined the laws in relation to the nature of each government, we must
investigate those which relate to its principle.
There is this difference between the nature and principle1 of government, that the former is that by which it is constituted, the latter that by which it is made to act. One is its particular structure, and the other the human passions which set it in
motion.
Now, laws ought no less to relate to the principle than to the nature of each government. We must, therefore, inquire into this principle, which shall be the subject of this third book.
2. Of the Principle of different Governments. I have already observed that it is the nature of a
republican government that either the
collective body of the people, or particular families, should be possessed of the supreme power; of a
monarchy, that the prince should have this power, but in the
execution of it should be directed by established laws; of a despotic government, that a single person should rule according to his own will and caprice. This enables me to discover their three principles; which are thence naturally derived. I shall begin with a
republican government, and in particular with that of democracy.
3. Of the Principle of Democracy. There is no great share of probity necessary to support a monarchical or despotic government. The force of laws in one, and the prince's arm in the other, are sufficient to direct and maintain the whole. But in a popular state, one spring more is necessary,
namely, virtue.
What I have here advanced is confirmed by the
unanimoustestimony of historians, and is extremely agreeable to the nature of things. For it is clear that in a
monarchy, where he who commands the
execution of the laws generally thinks himself above them, there is less need of virtue than in a popular government, where the person
entrusted with the
execution of the laws is sensible of his being subject to their direction.
Clear is it also that a monarch who, through bad advice or indolence, ceases to enforce the
execution of the laws, may easily repair the evil; he has only to follow other advice; or to shake off this indolence. But when, in a popular government, there is a
suspension of the laws, as this can proceed only from the
corruption of the republic, the state is certainly undone.
A very droll spectacle it was in the last century to behold the impotent efforts of the English towards the establishment of democracy. As they who had a share in the direction of public affairs were void of virtue; as their ambition was inffamed by the success of the most
daring of their members;2 as the
prevailing parties were successively
animated by the spirit of
faction, the government was
continually changing: the people, amazed at so many revolutions, in vain attempted to erect a
commonwealth. At length, when the country had
undergone the most violent shocks, they were obliged to have
recourse to the very government which they had so wantonly proscribed.
When Sylla thought of restoring Rome to her liberty, this unhappy city was
incapable of receiving that blessing. She had only the feeble remains of virtue, which were
continually diminishing. Instead of being roused from her lethargy by C?sar, Tiberius, Caius Claudius, Nero, and Domitian, she riveted every day her chains; if she struck some blows, her aim was at the
tyrant, not at the tyranny.
The
politic Greeks, who lived under a popular government, knew no other support than virtue. The modern inhabitants of that country are entirely taken up with manufacture, commerce, finances, opulence, and luxury.
When virtue is banished, ambition invades the minds of those who are disposed to receive it, and
avarice possesses the whole
community. The objects of their desires are changed; what they were fond of before has become
indifferent; they were free while under the
restraint" title="n.抑制;管束;克制">
restraint of laws, but they would fain now be free to act against law; and as each citizen is like a slave who has run away from his master, that which was a maxim of
equity he calls rigour; that which was a rule of action he styles constraint; and to
precaution he gives the name of fear. Frugality, and not the thirst of gain, now passes for
avarice. Formerly the wealth of individuals constituted the public treasure; but now this has become the patrimony of private persons. The members of the
commonwealth riot on the public spoils, and its strength is only the power of a few, and the licence of many.
Athens was possessed of the same number of forces when she triumphed so
gloriously as when with such infamy she was enslaved. She had twenty thousand citizens3 when she defended the Greeks against the Persians, when she contended for empire with Sparta, and invaded Sicily. She had twenty thousand when Demetrius Phalereus numbered them4 as slaves are told by the head in a market-place. When Philip attempted to lord it over Greece, and appeared at the gates of Athens5 she had even then lost nothing but time. We may see in Demosthenes how difficult it was to awaken her; she dreaded Philip, not as the enemy of her liberty, but of her pleasures.6 This famous city, which had withstood so many defeats, and having been so often destroyed had as often risen out of her ashes, was
overthrown at Ch?ronea, and at one blow deprived of all hopes of resource. What does it avail her that Philip sends back her prisoners, if he does not return her men? It was ever after as easy to triumph over the forces of Athens as it had been difficult to
subdue her virtue.
How was it possible for Carthage to maintain her ground? When Hannibal, upon his being made pr?tor, endeavoured to
hinder the magistrates from plundering the republic, did not they complain of him to the Romans? Wretches, who would fain be citizens without a city, and be beholden for their riches to their very destroyers! Rome soon insisted upon having three hundred of their principal citizens as hostages; she obliged them next to surrender their arms and ships; and then she declared war.7 From the desperate efforts of this defenceless city, one may judge of what she might have performed in her full
vigour, and assisted by virtue.
4. Of the Principle of Aristocracy. As virtue is necessary in a popular government, it is
requisite also in an
aristocracy. True it is that in the latter it is not so absolutely
requisite.
The people, who in respect to the
nobility are the same as the subjects with regard to a monarch, are
restrained by their laws. They have, therefore, less occasion for virtue than the people in a democracy. But how are the
nobility to be
restrained? They who are to execute the laws against their colleagues will immediately perceive that they are acting against themselves. Virtue is therefore necessary in this body, from the very nature of the constitution.
An
aristocratic government has an
inherentvigour, unknown to democracy. The nobles form a body, who by their
prerogative, and for their own particular interest,
restrain the people; it is sufficient that there are laws in being to see them executed.
But easy as it may be for the body of the nobles to
restrain the people, it is difficult to
restrain themselves.8 Such is the nature of this constitution, that it seems to subject the very same persons to the power of the laws, and at the same time to
exempt them.
Now such a body as this can
restrain itself only in two ways; either by a very
eminent virtue, which puts the
nobility in some measure on a level with the people, and may be the means of forming a great republic; or by an
inferior virtue, which puts them at least upon a level with one another, and upon this their
preservation depends.
Moderation is therefore the very soul of this government; a
moderation, I mean, founded on virtue, not that which proceeds from indolence and pusillanimity.
5. That Virtue is not the Principle of a Monarchical Government. In monarchies,
policy effects great things with as little virtue as possible. Thus in the nicest machines, art has reduced the number of movements, springs, and wheels.
The state subsists
independently of the love of our country, of the thirst of true glory, of self-denial, of the sacrifice of our dearest interests, and of all those
heroic virtues which we admire in the ancients, and to us are known only by tradition.
The laws supply here the place of those virtues; they are by no means wanted, and the state dispenses with them: an action performed here in secret is in some measure of no consequence.
Though all crimes be in their own nature public, yet there is a distinction between crimes really public and those that are private, which are so called because they are more
injurious to individuals than to the
community.
Now in republics private crimes are more public, that is, they attack the constitution more than they do individuals; and in monarchies, public crimes are more private, that is, they are more prejudicial to private people than to the constitution.
I beg that no one will be offended with what I have been
saying; my observations are founded on the
unanimoustestimony of historians. I am not ignorant that
virtuous princes are so very rare; but I venture to
affirm that in a
monarchy it is extremely difficult for the people to be
virtuous.9
Let us compare what the historians of all ages have asserted
concerning the courts of monarchs; let us
recollect the conversations and sentiments of people of all countries, in respect to the wretched character of
courtiers, and we shall find that these are not airy speculations, but truths confirmed by a sad and
melancholy experience.
Ambition in
idleness; meanness mixed with pride; a desire of riches without industry; aversion to truth;
flattery, perfidy,
violation of engagements,
contempt of civil duties, fear of the prince's virtue, hope from his weakness, but, above all, a
perpetualridicule cast upon virtue, are, I think, the characteristics by which most
courtiers in all ages and countries have been constantly
distinguished. Now, it is
exceedingly difficult for the leading men of the nation to be knaves, and the
inferior sort to be honest; for the former to be cheats, and the latter to rest satisfied with being only dupes.
But if there should chance to be some
unlucky honest man10 among the people. Cardinal Richelieu, in his
political
testament, seems to hint that a prince should take care not to employ him.11 So true is it that virtue is not the spring of this government! It is not indeed excluded, but it is not the spring of government.
6. In what Manner Virtue is supplied in a Monarchical Government. But it is high time for me to have done with this subject, lest I should be suspected of writing a
satire against monarchical government. Far be it from me; if
monarchy wants one spring, it is provided with another. Honour, that is, the
prejudice of every person and rank, supplies the place of the
political virtue of which I have been
speaking, and is everywhere her representative: here it is capable of inspiring the most glorious actions, and, joined with the force of laws, may lead us to the end of government as well as virtue itself.
Hence, in well-regulated monarchies, they are almost all good subjects, and very few good men; for to be a good man12 a good intention is necessary,13 and we should love our country, not so much on our own account, as out of regard to the
community.
7. Of the Principle of Monarchy. A monarchical government supposes, as we have already observed, pre-eminences and ranks, as likewise a noble
descent. Now since it is the nature of honour to
aspire to preferments and titles, it is properly placed in this government.
Ambition is
pernicious in a republic. But in a
monarchy it has some good effects; it gives life to the government, and is attended with this advantage, that it is in no way dangerous, because it may be
continually checked.
It is with this kind of government as with the system of the
universe, in which there is a power that constantly repels all bodies from the centre, and a power of
gravitation that attracts them to it. Honour sets all the parts of the body
politic in
motion, and by its very action connects them; thus each individual advances the public good, while he only thinks of promoting his own interest.
True it is that, philosophically
speaking, it is a false honour which moves all the parts of the government; but even this false honour is as useful to the public as true honour could possibly be to private persons.
Is it not very
exacting to oblige men to perform the most difficult actions, such as require an extraordinary
exertion of
fortitude and resolution, without other
recompense than that of glory and applause?
8. That Honour is not the Principle of Despotic Government. Honour is far from being the principle of despotic government: mankind being here all upon a level, no one person can prefer himself to another; and as on the other hand they are all slaves, they can give themselves no sort of preference.
Besides, as honour has its laws and rules, as it knows not how to submit; as it depends in a great measure on a man's own caprice, and not on that of another person; it can be found only in countries in which the constitution is fixed, and where they are governed by settled laws.
How can despotism abide with honour? The one glories in the
contempt of life; and the other is founded on the power of
taking it away. How can honour, on the other hand, bear with despotism? The former has its fixed rules, and peculiar caprices; but the latter is directed by no rule, and its own caprices are subversive of all others.
Honour, therefore, a thing unknown in
arbitrary governments, some of which have not even a proper word to express it,14 is the
prevailing principle in monarchies; here it gives life to the whole body
politic, to the laws, and even to the virtues themselves.
9. Of the Principle of Despotic Government. As virtue is necessary in a republic, and in a
monarchy honour, so fear is necessary in a despotic government: with regard to virtue, there is no occasion for it, and honour would be extremely dangerous.
Here the immense power of the prince devolves entirely upon those whom he is pleased to
entrust with the administration. Persons capable of
setting a value upon themselves would be likely to create disturbances. Fear must therefore
depress their spirits, and
extinguish even the least sense of ambition.
A moderate government may, whenever it pleases, and without the least danger, relax its springs. It supports itself by the laws, and by its own
internal strength. But when a despotic prince ceases for one single moment to
uplift his arm, when he cannot instantly
demolish those whom he has
entrusted with the first employments,15 all is over: for as fear, the spring of this government, no longer subsists, the people are left without a protector.
It is probably in this sense the Cadis maintained that the Grand Seignior was not obliged to keep his word or oath, when he
limited thereby his authority.16
It is necessary that the people should be judged by laws, and the great men by the caprice of the prince, that the lives of the lowest subject should be safe, and the pasha's head ever in danger. We cannot mention these
monstrous governments without horror. The Sophi of Persia, dethroned in our days by Mahomet, the son of Miriveis, saw the constitution subverted before this resolution, because he had been too sparing of blood.17
History informs us that the
horrid cruelties of Domitian struck such a terror into the governors that the people recovered themselves a little during his reign.18 Thus a
torrent overflows one side of a country, and on the other leaves fields
untouched, where the eye is refreshed by the prospect of fine meadows.
10. Difference of Obedience in Moderate and Despotic Governments. In despotic states, the nature of government requires the most passive
obedience; and when once the prince's will is made known, it ought infallibly to produce its effect.
Here they have no limitations or restrictions, no mediums, terms, equivalents, or remonstrances; no change to propose: man is a creature that
blindly submits to the absolute will of the sovereign.
In a country like this they are no more allowed to represent their apprehensions of a future danger than to
impute their miscarriage to the capriciousness of fortune. Man's portion here, like that of beasts, is instinct, compliance, and punishment.
Little does it then avail to plead the sentiments of nature,
filial respect, conjugal or parental
tenderness, the laws of honour, or want of health; the order is given, and, that is sufficient.
In Persia, when the king has condemned a person, it is no longer
lawful to mention his name, or to intercede in his favour. Even if the prince were intoxicated, or non compos, the decree must be executed;19 otherwise he would
contradict himself, and the law admits of no
contradiction. This has been the way of thinking in that country in all ages; as the order which Ahasuerus gave, to exterminate the Jews, could not be revoked, they were allowed the liberty of defending themselves.
One thing, however, may be sometimes opposed to the prince's will,20
namely, religion. They will abandon, nay they will slay a parent, if the prince so commands; but he cannot oblige them to drink wine. The laws of religion are of a superior nature, because they bind the sovereign as well as the subject. But with respect to the law of nature, it is otherwise; the prince is no longer supposed to be a man.
In monarchical and moderate states, the power is
limited by its very spring, I mean by honour, which, like a monarch, reigns over the prince and his people. They will not
allege to their sovereign the laws of religion; a
courtier would be
apprehensive of rendering himself
ridiculous. But the laws of honour will be appealed to on all occasions. Hence arise the restrictions necessary to
obedience; honour is naturally subject to whims, by which the subject's
submission will be ever directed.
Though the manner of obeying be different in these two kinds of government, the power is the same. On which side soever the monarch turns, he inclines the scale, and is obeyed. The whole difference is that in a
monarchy the prince receives instruction, at the same time that his ministers have greater abilities, and are more versed in public affairs, than the ministers of a despotic government.
11. Reflections on the
preceding Chapters. Such are the principles of the three sorts of government: which does not imply that in a particular republic they actually are, but that they ought to be,
virtuous; nor does it prove that in a particular
monarchy they are actuated by honour, or in a particular despotic government by fear; but that they ought to be directed by these principles, otherwise the government is imperfect.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------