酷兔英语

章节正文

Book XXIV. Of Laws in relation to Religion Considered in Itself, and in its Doctrines

  1. Of Religion in General. As amidst several degrees of darkness we may form a judgment of those which are the least thick, and among precipices which are the least deep, so we may search among false religions for those that are most conformable to the welfare of society; for those which, though they have not the effect of leading men to the felicity of another life, may contribute most to their happiness in this.

  I shall examine, therefore, the several religions of the world, in relation only to the good they produce in civil society, whether I speak of that which has its root in heaven, or of those which spring from the earth.

  As in this work I am not a divine but a political writer, I may here advance things which are not otherwise true than as they correspond with a worldly manner of thinking, not as considered in their relation to truths of a more sublime nature.

  With regard to the true religion, a person of the least degree of impartiality must see that I have never pretended to make its interests submit to those of a political nature, but rather to unite them; now, in order to unite, it is necessary that we should know them.

  The Christian religion, which ordains that men should love each other, would, without doubt, have every nation blest with the best civil, the best political laws; because these, next to this religion, are the greatest good that men can give and receive.

  2. A Paradox of M. Bayle's. M. Bayle has pretended to prove1 that it is better to be an Atheist than an Idolater; that is, in other words, that it is less dangerous to have no religion at all than a bad one. "I had rather," said he, "it should be said of me that I had no existence than that I am a villain." This is only a sophism founded on this, that it is of no importance to the human race to believe that a certain man exists, whereas it is extremely useful for them to believe the existence of a God. From the idea of his non-existence immediately follows that of our independence; or, if we cannot conceive this idea, that of disobedience. To say that religion is not a restraining motive, because it does not always restrain, is equally absurd as to say that the civil laws are not a restraining motive. It is a false way of reasoning against religion to collect, in a large work, a long detail of the evils it has produced if we do not give at the same time an enumeration of the advantages which have flowed from it. Were I to relate all the evils that have arisen in the world from civil laws, from monarchy, and from republican government, I might tell of frightful things. Were it of no advantage for subjects to have religion, it would still be of some, if princes had it, and if they whitened with foam the only rein which can restrain those who fear not human laws.

  A prince who loves and fears religion is a lion, who stoops to the hand that strokes, or to the voice that appeases him. He who fears and hates religion is like the savage beast that growls and bites the chain which prevents his flying on the passenger. He who has no religion at all is that terrible animal who perceives his liberty only when he tears in pieces and when he devours.

  The question is not to know whether it would be better that a certain man or a certain people had no religion than to abuse what they have, but to know what is the least evil, that religion be sometimes abused, or that there be no such restraint as religion on mankind.

  To diminish the horror of Atheism, they lay too much to the charge of idolatry. It is far from being true that when the ancients raised altars to a particular vice, they intended to show that they loved the vice; this signified, on the contrary, that they hated it. When the Laced?monians erected a temple to Fear, it was not to show that this warlike nation desired that he would in the midst of battle possess the hearts of the Laced?monians. They had deities to whom they prayed not to inspire them with guilt; and others whom they besought to shield them from it.

  3. That a moderate Government is most agreeable to the Christian Religion, and a despotic Government to the Mahometan. The Christian religion is a stranger to mere despotic power. The mildness so frequently recommended in the Gospel is incompatible with the despotic rage with which a prince punishes his subjects, and exercises himself in cruelty.

  As this religion forbids the plurality of wives, its princes are less confined, less concealed from their subjects, and consequently have more humanity: they are more disposed to be directed by laws, and more capable of perceiving that they cannot do whatever they please.

  While the Mahometan princes incessantly give or receive death, the religion of the Christians renders their princes less timid, and consequently less cruel. The prince confides in his subjects, and the subjects in the prince. How admirable the religion which, while it only seems to have in view the felicity of the other life, continues the happiness of this!

  It is the Christian religion that, in spite of the extent of the empire and the influence of the climate, has hindered despotic power from being established in Ethiopia, and has carried into the heart of Africa the manners and laws of Europe.

  The heir to the empire of Ethiopia2 enjoys a principality and gives to other subjects an example of love and obedience. Not far thence may we see the Mahometan shutting up the children of the King of Sennar, at whose death the council sends to murder them, in favour of the prince who mounts the throne.

  Let us set before our eyes, on the one hand, the continual massacres of the kings and generals of the Greeks and Romans, and, on the other, the destruction of people and cities by those famous conquerors Timur Beg and Jenghiz Khan, who ravaged Asia, and we shall see that we owe to Christianity, in government, a certain political law; and in war, a certain law of nations - benefits which human nature can never sufficiently acknowledge.

  It is owing to this law of nations that among us victory leaves these great advantages to the conquered, life, liberty, laws, wealth, and always religion, when the conqueror is not blind to his own interest.

  We may truly say that the people of Europe are not at present more disunited than the people and the armies, or even the armies among themselves were, under the Roman empire when it had become a despotic and military government. On the one hand, the armies engaged in war against each other, and, on the other, they pillaged the cities, and divided or confiscated the lands.

  4. Consequences from the Character of the Christian Religion, and that of the Mahometan. From the characters of the Christian and Mahometan religions, we ought, without any further examination, to embrace the one and reject the other: for it is much easier to prove that religion ought to humanise the manners of men than that any particular religion is true.

  It is a misfortune to human nature when religion is given by a conqueror. The Mahometan religion, which speaks only by the sword, acts still upon men with that destructive spirit with which it was founded.

  The history of Sabbaco,3 one of the pastoral kings of Egypt, is very extraordinary. The tutelar god of Thebes, appearing to him in a dream, ordered him to put to death all the priests of Egypt. He judged that the gods were displeased at his being on the throne, since they commanded him to commit an action contrary to their ordinary pleasure; and therefore he retired into Ethiopia.

  5. That the Catholic Religion is most agreeable to a Monarchy, and the Protestant to a Republic. When a religion is introduced and fixed in a state, it is commonly such as is most suitable to the plan of government there established; for those who receive it, and those who are the cause of its being received, have scarcely any other idea of policy than that of the state in which they were born.

  When the Christian religion, two centuries ago, became unhappily divided into Catholic and Protestant, the people of the north embraced the Protestant, and those of the south adhered still to the Catholic.

  The reason is plain: the people of the north have, and will for ever have, a spirit of liberty and independence, which the people of the south have not; and therefore a religion which has no visible head is more agreeable to the independence of the climate than that which has one.

  In the countries themselves where the Protestant religion became established, the revolutions were made pursuant to the several plans of political government. Luther having great princes on his side would never have been able to make them relish an ecclesiastical authority that had no exterior pre-eminence; while Calvin, having to do with people who lived under republican governments, or with obscure citizens in monarchies, might very well avoid establishing dignities and preferments.

  Each of these two religions was believed to be perfect; the Calvinist judging his most conformable to what Christ had said, and the Lutheran to what the Apostles had practised.

  6. Another of M. Bayle's Paradoxes. M. Bayle, after having abused all religions, endeavours to sully Christianity: he boldly asserts that true Christians cannot form a government of any duration. Why not? Citizens of this profession being infinitely" title="ad.无限地;无穷地">infinitely enlightened with respect to the various duties of life, and having the warmest zeal to fulfil them, must be perfectly sensible of the rights of natural defence. The more they believe themselves indebted to religion, the more they would think due to their country. The principles of Christianity, deeply engraved on the heart, would be infinitely" title="ad.无限地;无穷地">infinitely more powerful than the false honour of monarchies, than the humane virtues of republics, or the servile fear of despotic states.

  It is astonishing that this great man should not be able to distinguish between the orders for the establishment of Christianity and Christianity itself; and that he should be liable to be charged with not knowing the spirit of his own religion. When the legislator, instead of laws, has given counsels, this is because he knew that if these counsels were ordained as laws they would be contrary to the spirit of the laws themselves.

  7. Of the Laws of Perfection in Religion. Human laws, made to direct the will, ought to give precepts, and not counsels; religion, made to influence the heart, should give many counsels, and few precepts.

  When, for instance, it gives rules, not for what is good, but for what is better; not to direct to what is right, but to what is perfect, it is expedient that these should be counsels, and not laws: for perfection can have no relation to the universality of men or things. Besides, if these were laws, there would be a necessity for an infinite number of others, to make people observe the first. Celibacy was advised by Christianity; when they made it a law in respect to a certain order of men, it became necessary to make new ones every day, in order to oblige those men to observe it.4 The legislator wearied himself, and he wearied society, to make men execute by precept what those who love perfection would have executed as counsel.

  8. Of the Connection between the moral Laws and those of Religion. In a country so unfortunate as to have a religion that God has not revealed, it is necessary for it to be agreeable to morality; because even a false religion is the best security we can have of the probity of men.

  The principal points of religion of the inhabitants of Pegu5 are, not to commit murder, not to steal, to avoid uncleanliness, not to give the least uneasiness to their neighbour, but to do him, on the contrary, all the good in their power. With these rules they think they should be saved in any religion whatsoever. Hence it proceeds that those people, though poor and proud, behave with gentleness and compassion to the unhappy.

  9. Of the Essenes. The Essenes6 made a vow to observe justice to mankind, to do no ill to any person, upon whatsoever account, to keep faith with all the world, to hate injustice, to command with modesty, always to side with truth, and to fly from all unlawful gain.

  10. Of the Sect of Stoics. The several sects of philosophy among the ancients were a species of religion. Never were any principles more worthy of human nature, and more proper to form the good man, than those of the Stoics; and if I could for a moment cease to think that I am a Christian, I should not be able to hinder myself from ranking the destruction of the sect of Zeno among the misfortunes that have befallen the human race.

  It carried to excess only those things in which there is true greatness - the contempt of pleasure and of pain.

  It was this sect alone that made citizens; this alone that made great men; this alone great emperors.

  Laying aside for a moment revealed truths, let us search through all nature, and we shall not find a nobler object than the Antoninuses; even Julian himself - Julian (a commendation thus wrested from me will not render me an accomplice of his apostasy) - no, there has not been a prince since his reign more worthy to govern mankind.

  While the Stoics looked upon riches, human grandeur, grief, disquietudes, and pleasures as vanity, they were entirely employed in labouring for the happiness of mankind, and in exercising the duties of society. It seems as if they regarded that sacred spirit, which they believed to dwell within them, as a kind of favourable providencewatchful over the human race.

  Born for society, they all believed that it was their destiny to labour for it; with so much the less fatigue, their rewards were all within themselves. Happy by their philosophy alone, it seemed as if only the happiness of others could increase theirs.

  11. Of Contemplation. Men being made to preserve, to nourish, to clothe themselves, and do all the actions of society, religion ought not to give them too contemplative a life.7

  The Mahometans become speculative by habit; they pray five times a day, and each time they are obliged to cast behind them everything which has any concern with this world: this forms them for speculation. Add to this that indifference for all things which is inspired by the doctrine of unalterable fate.

  If other causes besides these concur to disengage their affections; for instance, if the severity of the government, if the laws concerning the property of land, give them a precarious spirit - all is lost.

  The religion of the Gaurs formerly rendered Persia a flourishing kingdom; it corrected the bad effects of despotic power. The same empire is now destroyed by the Mahometan religion.

  12. Of Penances. Penances ought to be joined with the idea of labour, not with that of idleness; with the idea of good, not with that of supereminence; with the idea of frugality, not with that of avarice.

  13. Of inexpiable Crimes. It appears from a. passage of the books of the pontiffs, quoted by Cicero,8 that they had among the Romans inexpiable crimes:9 and it is on this that Zozymus founds the narration so proper to blacken the motives of Constantine's conversion; and Julian, that bitter raillery on this conversion in his C?sars.

  The Pagan religion indeed, which prohibited only some of the grosser crimes, and which stopped the hand but meddled not with the heart, might have crimes that were inexpiable; but a religion which bridles all the passions; which is not more jealous of actions than of thoughts and desires; which holds us not by a few chains but by an infinite number of threads; which, leaving human justice aside, establishes another kind of justice; which is so ordered as to lead us continually from repentance to love, and from love to repentance; which puts between the judge and the criminal a greater mediator, between the just and the mediator a great judge - a religion like this ought not to have inexpiable crimes. But while it gives fear and hope to all, it makes us sufficiently sensible that though there is no crime in its own nature inexpiable, yet a whole criminal life may be so; that it is extremely dangerous to affront mercy by new crimes and new expiations; that an uneasiness on account of ancient debts, from which we are never entirely free, ought to make us afraid of contracting new ones, of filling up the measure, and going even to that point where paternal goodness is limited.

  14. In what Manner Religion has an Influence on Civil Laws. As both religion and the civil laws ought to have a peculiar tendency to render men good citizens, it is evident that when one of these deviates from this end, the tendency of the other ought to be strengthened. The less severity there is in religion, the more there ought to be in the civil laws.

  Thus the reigning religion of Japan having few doctrines, and proposing neither future rewards nor punishments, the laws to supply these defects have been made with the spirit of severity, and are executed with an extraordinary punctuality.

  When the doctrine of necessity is established by religion, the penalties of the laws ought to be more severe, and the magistrate more vigilant; to the end that men who would otherwise become abandoned might be determined by these motives; but it is quite otherwise where religion has established the doctrine of liberty.

  From the inactivity of the soul springs the Mahometan doctrine of predestination, and from this doctrine of predestination springs the inactivity of the soul. This, they say, is in the decrees of God; they must therefore indulge their repose. In a case like this, the magistrate ought to waken by the laws those who are lulled asleep by religion.

  When religion condemns things which the civil laws ought to permit, there is danger lest the civil laws, on the other hand, should permit what religion ought to condemn. Either of these is a constant proof of a want of true ideas of that harmony and proportion which ought to subsist between both.

  Thus the Tartars under Jenghiz Khan,10 among whom it was a sin and even a capital crime to put a knife in the fire, to lean against a whip, to strike a horse with his bridle, to break one bone with another, did not believe it to be any sin to break their word, to seize upon another man's goods, to do an injury to a person, or to commit murder. In a word, laws which render that necessary which is only indifferent have this inconvenience, that they make those things indifferent which are absolutely necessary.

  The people of Formosa believe11 that there is a kind of hell, but it is to punish those who at certain seasons have not gone naked, who have dressed in calico and not in silk, who have presumed to look for oysters, or who have undertaken any business without consulting the song of birds; while drunkenness and debauchery are not regarded as crimes. They believe even that the debauches of their children are agreeable to their gods.
关键字:英文版论法的精神
生词表:
  • amidst [ə´midst] 移动到这儿单词发声 prep.=amid 四级词汇
  • felicity [fi´lisiti] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.幸福;(措词)适当 六级词汇
  • worldly [´wə:ldli] 移动到这儿单词发声 a.现世的;世俗的 四级词汇
  • sublime [sə´blaim] 移动到这儿单词发声 a.崇高的,伟大的 四级词汇
  • arisen [ə´rizn] 移动到这儿单词发声 arise的过去分词 四级词汇
  • monarchy [´mɔnəki] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.君主政治;君主国 四级词汇
  • republican [ri´pʌblikən] 移动到这儿单词发声 a.共和国的 n.共和论者 四级词汇
  • idolatry [ai´dɔlətri] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.偶像崇拜;过度崇信 六级词汇
  • warlike [´wɔ:laik] 移动到这儿单词发声 a.战争的;好战的 四级词汇
  • besought [bi´sɔ:t] 移动到这儿单词发声 beseech过去式(分词) 四级词汇
  • incessantly [in´sesntli] 移动到这儿单词发声 ad.不断地,不停地 六级词汇
  • principality [,prinsi´pæliti] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.公国;封邑 六级词汇
  • destructive [di´strʌktiv] 移动到这儿单词发声 a.破坏性的 四级词汇
  • pastoral [´pɑ:stərəl] 移动到这儿单词发声 a.牧(羊)人的 n.田园诗 四级词汇
  • retired [ri´taiəd] 移动到这儿单词发声 a.退休的;通职的 六级词汇
  • policy [´pɔlisi] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.政策;权谋;保险单 四级词汇
  • ecclesiastical [i,kli:zi´æstikəl] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.基督教会的;教士的 六级词汇
  • exterior [ik´stiəriə] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.&a.外表(的) 四级词汇
  • duration [djuə´reiʃən] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.持久;持续期间 六级词汇
  • infinitely [´infinitli] 移动到这儿单词发声 ad.无限地;无穷地 四级词汇
  • indebted [in´detid] 移动到这儿单词发声 a.负债的;感恩的 六级词汇
  • humane [hju:´mein] 移动到这儿单词发声 a.有人情的,高尚的 六级词汇
  • legislator [´ledʒisleitə] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.立法者 六级词汇
  • expedient [ik´spi:diənt] 移动到这儿单词发声 a.合适的 n.权宜之计 四级词汇
  • precept [´pri:sept] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.箴言;教训;规则 四级词汇
  • morality [mə´ræliti] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.道德;教训;伦理学 四级词汇
  • uneasiness [ʌn´i:zinis] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.不安,担忧;不自在 四级词汇
  • whatsoever [,wɔtsəu´evə] 移动到这儿单词发声 (强势语)=whatever 四级词汇
  • gentleness [´dʒentlnis] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.温和,温柔 四级词汇
  • compassion [kəm´pæʃən] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.同情;怜悯 四级词汇
  • modesty [´mɔdisti] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.谨慎;端庄;羞怯 四级词汇
  • befallen [bi´fɔ:lən] 移动到这儿单词发声 befall的过去分词 四级词汇
  • commendation [,kɔmən´deiʃən] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.称赞,表扬;推荐 六级词汇
  • grandeur [´grændʒə] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.伟大;富丽;壮观 四级词汇
  • providence [´prɔvidəns] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.天意,天命,上帝 四级词汇
  • watchful [´wɔtʃfəl] 移动到这儿单词发声 a.注意的;戒备的 四级词汇
  • contemplation [,kɔntem´pleiʃən] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.注视;冥想;打算 四级词汇
  • speculative [´spekjulətiv] 移动到这儿单词发声 a.臆测的;投机的 六级词汇
  • severity [si´veriti] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.严厉;严重;苛刻 四级词汇
  • precarious [pri´keəriəs] 移动到这儿单词发声 a.不安定的;危险的 四级词汇
  • idleness [´aidlnis] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.懒;闲着不干事 四级词汇
  • blacken [´blækən] 移动到这儿单词发声 v.(使)变黑,诽谤 四级词汇
  • conversion [kən´və:ʃən] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.转化;变换;皈依 四级词汇
  • repentance [ri´pentəns] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.悔悟,悔改;忏悔 六级词汇
  • affront [ə´frʌnt] 移动到这儿单词发声 vt.&n.(当众)侮辱 六级词汇
  • paternal [pə´tə:nl] 移动到这儿单词发声 a.(象)父亲的;父方的 六级词汇
  • abandoned [ə´bændənd] 移动到这儿单词发声 a.被抛弃的;无约束的 六级词汇
  • subsist [səb´sist] 移动到这儿单词发声 vi.生存;维持生命 六级词汇
  • inconvenience [,inkən´vi:niəns] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.不方便;打扰 四级词汇
  • calico [´kælikəu] 移动到这儿单词发声 n.白棉布;印花布 四级词汇



章节正文