35. Of the Costs. In former times no one was condemned in the lay courts of France to the payment of costs.[257] The party cast was sufficiently punished by pecuniary fines to the lord and his peers. From the manner of
proceeding by
judicialcombat it followed, that the party condemned and deprived of life and fortune was punished as much as he could be: and in the other cases of the
judicialcombat, there were fines sometimes fixed, and sometimes
dependent on the disposition of the lord, which were sufficient to make people dread the consequences of suits. The same may be said of causes that were not
decided by
combat. As the lord had the chief profits, so he was also at the chief expense, either to assemble his peers, or to enable them to proceed to judgment. Besides, as disputes were generally determined at the same place, and almost always at the same time, without that
infinite multitude of writings which afterwards followed, there was no necessity of allowing costs to the parties.
The custom of
appeals naturally introduced that of giving costs. Thus D嶨ontaines says,[258] that when they
appealed by written law, that is, when they followed the new laws of St. Louis, they gave costs; but that in the ordinary practice, which did not permit them to
appeal without falsifying the judgment, no costs were allowed. They obtained only a fine, and the possession for a year and a day of the thing contested, if the cause was remanded to the lord.
But when the number of
appeals increased from the new facility of
appealing;[259] when by the frequent usage of those
appeals from one court to another, the parties were
continually" title="ad.不断地,频繁地">
continually removed from the place of their residence; when the new method of
procedure multiplied and prolonged the suits; when the art of eluding the very justest demands became
refined; when the parties at law knew how to fly only in order to be followed; when plaints were ruinous and defence easy; when the arguments were lost in whole volumes of words and writings; when the kingdom was filled with limbs of the law, who were strangers to justice; when knavery found
encouragement at the very place where it did not find protection; then it was necessary to deter litigious people by the fear of costs. They were obliged to pay costs for the judgment and for the means they had employed to elude it. Charles the Fair made a general
ordinance on that subject.[260]
36. Of the public Prosecutor. As by the Salic, Ripuarian, and other
barbarous laws, crimes were punished with pecuniary fines; they had not in those days, as we have at present, a public officer who had the care of criminal
prosecutions. And, indeed, the issue of all causes being reduced to the
reparation of injuries, every
prosecution was in some measure civil, and might be managed by any one. On the other hand, the Roman law had popular forms for the
prosecution of crimes which were
inconsistent with the functions of a public prosecutor.
The custom of
judicialcombats was no less opposite to this idea; for who is it that would choose to be a public prosecutor and to make himself every man's champion against all the world?
I find in the collection of formulas, inserted by Muratori in the laws of the Lombards, that under our princes of the second race there was an advocate for the public prosecutor.[261] But
whoever pleases to read the entire collection of these formulas will find that there was a total difference between such officers and those we now call the public prosecutor, our attorneys-general, our king's solicitors, or our solicitors for the
nobility. The former were rather agents to the public for the management of political and domestic affairs, than for the civil. And, indeed, we did not find in those formulas that they were entrusted with criminal
prosecutions, or with causes relating to minors, to churches, or to the condition of any one.
I said that the establishment of a public prosecutor was repugnant to the usage of
judicialcombats. I find,
notwithstanding, in one of those formulas, an advocate for the public prosecutor, who had the liberty to fight. Muratori has placed it just after the constitution of Henry I, for which it was made.[262] In this constitution it is said, "That if any man kills his father, his brother, or any of his other relatives, he shall lose their succession, which shall pass to the other relatives, and his own property shall go to the
exchequer." Now it was in suing for the estate which had devolved to the
exchequer, that the advocate for the public prosecutor, by whom its rights were defended, had the privilege of fighting: this case fell within the general rule.
We see in those formulas the advocate for the public prosecutor
proceeding against a person who had taken a robber, but had not brought him before the count;[263] against another who had raised an
insurrection or
tumult against the count;[264] against another who had saved a man's life whom the count had ordered to be put to death;[265] against the advocate of some churches, whom the count had commanded to bring a robber before him, but had not obeyed;[266] against another who had revealed the king's secret to strangers;[267] against another, who with open violence had attacked the emperor's commissary;[268] against another who had been guilty of
contempt to the emperor's rescripts, and he was prosecuted either by the emperor's advocate or by the emperor himself;[269] against another who refused to accept of the prince's coin;[270] in fine, this advocate sued for things which by the law were adjudged to the
exchequer.[271]
But in criminal causes, we never meet with the advocate for the public prosecutor; not even where duels are used;[272] not even in the case of incendiaries;[273] not even when the judge is killed on his bench;[274] not even in causes relating to the conditions of persons,[275] to liberty and slavery.[276]
These formulas are made, not only for the laws of the Lombards, but likewise for the capitularies added to them, so that we have no reason to doubt of their giving us the practice observed with regard to this subject under our princes of the second race.
It is obvious that these advocates for a public prosecutor must have ended with our second race of kings, in the same manner as the king's commissioners in the provinces; because there was no longer a general law nor general
exchequer, and because there were no longer any counts in the provinces to hold the assizes, and, of course, there were no more of those officers whose principal function was to support the authority of the counts.
As the usage of
combats became more frequent under the third race, it did not allow of any such thing as a public prosecutor. Hence Boutillier, in his Somme Rurale,
speaking of the officers of justice, takes notice only of the bailiffs, the peers and serjeants. See the Institutions[277] and Beaumanoir[278]
concerning the manner in which
prosecutions were managed in those days.
I find in the laws of James II, King of Majorca,[279] a creation of the office of king's attorney-general, with the very same functions as are exercised at present by the officers of that name among us. It is
manifest that this office was not instituted till we had changed the form of our judiciary
proceedings.
37. In what Manner the Institutions of St. Louis fell into Oblivion. It was the fate of the Institutions that their origin, progress, and decline were comprised within a very short period.
I shall make a few reflections upon this subject. The code we have now under the name of St. Louis' Institutions was never designed as a law for the whole kingdom, though such a design is mentioned in the
preface. The compilation is a general code, which determines all points relating to civil affairs, to the
disposal of property by will or otherwise, the dowries and privileges of women, and emoluments and privileges of fiefs, with the affairs in relation to the police, &c. Now, to give a general body of civil laws, at a time when each city, town, or village, had its customs, was attempting to subvert in one moment all the particular laws then in force in every part of the kingdom. To reduce all the particular customs to a general one would be a very inconsiderate thing, even at present when our princes find everywhere the most passive
obedience. But if it be true that we ought not to change when the inconveniences are equal to the advantages, much less should we change when the advantages are small and the inconveniences immense. Now, if we attentively consider the situation which the kingdom was in at that time, when every lord was puffed up with the notion of his
sovereignty and power, we shall find that to attempt a general
alteration of the received laws and customs must be a thing that could never enter into the heads of those who were then in the administration.
What I have been
saying proves likewise that this code of institutions was not confirmed in parliament by the barons and magistrates of the kingdom, as is mentioned in a
manuscript of the town-hall of Amiens, quoted by M. Du Cange.[280] We find in other
manuscripts that this code was given by St. Louis in the year 1270, before he set out for Tunis. But this fact is not truer than the other; for St. Louis set out upon that expedition in 1269, as M. Du Cange observes:
whence he concludes that this code might have been published in his absence. But this I say is impossible. How can St. Louis be imagined to have pitched upon the time of his absence for transacting an affair which would have been a sowing of troubles, and might have produced not only changes, but revolutions? An enterprise of that kind had need, more than any other, of being closely pursued, and could not be the work of a feeble regency,
composed moreover of lords, whose interest it was that it should not succeed. These were Mathieu, Abbot of St. Denis, Simon of Clermont, Count of Nesle, and, in case of death, Philip, Bishop of Evreux, and Jean, Count of Ponthieu. We have seen above[281] that the Count of Ponthieu opposed the
execution of a new judiciary order in his
lordship.
Thirdly, I
affirm it to be very probable that the code now extant is quite a different thing from St. Louis' Institutions, It cites the Institutions; therefore it is a comment upon the Institutions, and not the institutions themselves. Besides, Beaumanoir, who frequently makes mention of St. Louis' Institutions, quotes only some particular laws of that prince, and not this compilation. D嶨ontaines,[282] who wrote in that prince's reign, makes mention of the first two times that his Institutions on
judicialproceedings were put in
execution, as of a thing long since elapsed. The institutions of St. Louis were prior, therefore, to the compilation I am now
speaking of, which from their rigour, and their adopting the
erroneousprefaces inserted by some ignorant persons in that work, could not have been published before the last year of St. Louis or even not till after his death.
38. The same Subject continued. What is this compilation then which goes at present under the name of St. Louis' Institutions? What is this obscure, confused, and ambiguous code, where the French law is
continually" title="ad.不断地,频繁地">
continually mixed with the Roman, where a
legislator speaks and yet we see a
civilian, where we find a complete digest of all cases and points of the civil law? To understand this thoroughly, we must transfer ourselves in imagination to those times.
St. Louis,
seeing the abuses in the jurisprudence of his time, endeavoured to give the people a dislike to it. With this view he made several regulations for the court of his demesnes, and for those of his barons. And such was his success that Beaumanoir, who wrote a little after the death of that prince, informs us[283] that the manner of
trying causes which had been established by St. Louis obtained in a great number of the courts of the barons.
Thus this prince attained his end, though his regulations for the courts of the lords were not designed as a general law for the kingdom, but as a model which every one might follow, and would even find his advantage in it. He removed the bad practice by showing them a better. When it appeared that his courts, and those of some lords, had chosen a form of
proceeding more natural, more reasonable, more conformable to
morality, to religion, to the public tranquillity, and to the security of person and property, this form was soon adopted, and the other rejected.
To
allure when it is rash to
constrain, to win by
pleasing means when it is
improper to exert authority, shows the man of abilities. Reason has a natural, and even a tyrannical sway; it meets with resistance, but this very resistance constitutes its triumph; for after a short struggle it commands an entire
submission.
St. Louis, in order to give a distaste of the French jurisprudence, caused the books of the Roman law to be translated; by which means they were made known to the lawyers of those times. D嶨ontaines, who is the oldest law writer we have, made great use of those Roman laws.[284] His work is, in some measure, a result from the ancient French jurisprudence, of the laws or Institutions of St. Louis, and of the Roman law. Beaumanoir made very little use of the latter; but he reconciled the ancient French laws to the regulations of St. Louis.
I have a notion, therefore, that the law book known by the name of the Institutions was
compiled by some bailiffs, with the same design as that of the authors of those two Works, and especially of D嶨ontaines. The title of this work mentions that it is written according to the usage of Paris, Orleans, and the court of Barony; and the preamble says that it treats of the usage of the whole kingdom, of Anjou and of the court of Barony. It is plain that this work was made for Paris, Orleans and Anjou, as the works of Beaumanoir and D嶨ontaines were framed for the counties of Clermont and Vermandois; and as it appears from Beaumanoir that
divers laws of St. Louis had been received in the courts of Barony, the
compiler was in the right to say that his work
related also to those courts.[285]
It is
manifest that the person who
composed this work
compiled the customs of the country together with the laws and Institutions of St. Louis. This is a very valuable work, because it contains the ancient customs of Anjou, the Institutions of St. Louis, as they were then in use; and, in fine, the whole practice of the ancient French law.
The difference between this work and those of D嶨ontaines and Beaumanoir is its
speaking in
imperative terms as a
legislator; and this might be right, since it was a medley of written customs and laws.
There was an intrinsic
defect in this compilation; it formed an amphibious code, in which the French and Roman laws were mixed, and where things were joined that were in no relation, but often contradictory to each other.
I am not ignorant that the French courts of vassals or peers; the judgments without power of
appealing to another
tribunal; the manner of pronouncing sentence by these words "I condemn" or "I absolve,"[286] had some
conformity to the popular judgments of the Romans. But they made very little use of that ancient jurisprudence; they rather chose that which was afterwards introduced by the emperor, in order to
regulate, limit, correct, and extend the French jurisprudence.
39. The same Subject continued. The judiciary forms introduced by St. Louis fell into disuse. This prince had not so much in view the thing itself, that is, the best manner of
trying causes, as the best manner of supplying the ancient practice of trial. The principal intent was to give a disrelish of the ancient jurisprudence, and the next to form a new one. But when the inconveniences of the latter appeared, another soon succeeded.
The Institutions of St. Louis did not, therefore, so much change the French jurisprudence as they afforded the means of changing it; they opened new
tribunals, or rather ways to come at them. And when once the public had easy
access to the superior courts, the judgments which before constituted only the usages of a particular
lordship formed a universal digest. By means of the Institutions, they had obtained general decisions, which were entirely
wanting in the kingdom; when the building was finished, they let the scaffold fall to the ground.
Thus the Institutions produced effects which could hardly be expected from a
masterpiece of legislation. To prepare great changes whole ages are sometimes
requisite; the events ripen, and the revolutions follow.
The parliament judged in the last resort of almost all the affairs of the kingdom. Before,[287] it took cognizance only of disputes between the dukes, counts, barons, bishops, abbots, or between the king and his vassals,[288] rather in the relation they bore to the political than to the civil order. They were soon obliged to render it permanent, whereas it used to be held only a few times in a year: and, in fine, a great number were created; in order to be sufficient for the decision of all manner of causes.
No sooner had the parliament become a fixed body, than they began to
compile its decrees. Jean de Monluc, in the reign of Philip the Fair, made a collection which at present is known by the name of the Olim registers.[289]
40. In what Manner the judiciary Forms were borrowed from the Decretals. But how comes it, some will ask, that when the Institutions were laid aside, the
judicial forms of the canon law should be preferred to those of the Roman? It was because they had constantly before their eyes the ecclesiastic courts, which followed the forms of the canon law, and they knew of no court that followed those of the Roman law. Besides, the limits of the spiritual and temporal
jurisdiction were at that time very little understood; there were people who sued
indifferently[290] and causes that were tried
indifferently, in either court.[291] It seems[292] as if the temporal
jurisdiction reserved no other cases
exclusively to itself than the judgment of
feudal matters,[293] and of such crimes committed by laymen as did not relate to religion. For[294] if on the account of conventions and contracts, they had occasion to sue in a temporal court, the parties might of their own accord proceed before the spiritual
tribunals; and as the latter had not a power to oblige the temporal court to execute the sentence, they commanded
submission by means of excommunications. Under those circumstances, when they wanted to change the course of
proceedings in the temporal court, they took that of the spiritual
tribunals, because they knew it; but did not
meddle with that of the Roman law, by reason they were strangers to it: for in point of practice people know only what is really practised.
41. Flux and Reflux of the ecclesiastic and temporal Jurisdiction. The civil power being in the hands of an
infinite number of lords, it was an easy matter for the ecclesiastic
jurisdiction to gain daily a greater extent. But as the ecclesiastic courts weakened those of the lords, and contributed thereby to give strength to the royal
jurisdiction, the latter gradually checked the
jurisdiction of the
clergy. The parliament, which in its form of
proceedings had adopted whatever was good and useful in the spiritual courts, soon perceived nothing else but the abuses which had crept into those
tribunals; and as the royal
jurisdiction gained ground every day, it grew every day more capable of correcting those abuses. And, indeed, they were
intolerable; without enumerating them I shall refer the reader to Beaumanoir, to Boutillier and to the
ordinances of our kings.[295] I shall mention only two in which the public interest was more directly
concerned. These abuses we know by the decrees that reformed them; they had been introduced in the times of the darkest ignorance, and upon the breaking out of the first gleam of light, they vanished. From the silence of the
clergy it may be presumed that they forwarded this reformation: which,
considering the nature of the human mind, deserves
commendation. Every man that died without bequeathing a part of his estate to the church, which was called dying "without confession," was deprived of the sacrament and of Christian burial. If he died intestate, his relatives were obliged to prevail upon the bishop that he would, jointly with them, name proper arbiters to determine what sum the deceased ought to have given, in case he had made a will. People could not lie together the first night of their nuptials, or even the two following nights, without having
previously purchased leave; these, indeed, were the best three nights to choose; for as to the others, they were not worth much. All this was redressed by the parliament: we find in the glossary of the French law,[296] by Ragau, the decree which it published against the Bishop of Amiens.[297]
I return to the beginning of my chapter. Whenever we observe in any age or government the different bodies of the state endeavouring to increase their authority, and to take particular advantages of each other, we should be often
mistaken were we to consider their encroachments as an evident mark of their
corruption" title="n.腐化;贪污;贿赂">
corruption. Through a fatality
inseparable from human nature,
moderation in great men is very rare: and as it is always much easier to push on force in the direction in which it moves than to stop its movement, so in the superior class of the people, it is less difficult, perhaps, to find men extremely
virtuous, than extremely prudent.
The human mind feels such an
exquisite pleasure in the exercise of power; even those who are lovers of virtue are so excessively fond of themselves that there is no man so happy as not still to have reason to
mistrust his honest intentions; and, indeed, our actions depend on so many things that it is
infinitely easier to do good, than to do it well.
42. The Revival of the Roman Law, and the Result thereof. Change of Tribunals. Upon the discovery of Justinian's digest towards the year 1137, the Roman law seemed to rise out of its ashes. Schools were then established in Italy, where it was
publicly taught; they had already the Justinian code and the Novell? I mentioned before that this code had been so
favourably received in that country as to
eclipse the law of the Lombards.
The Italian doctors brought the law of Justinian into France, where they had only the Theodosian code;[298] because Justinian's laws were not made till after the settlement of the Barbarians in Gaul.[299] This law met with some opposition: but it stood its ground
notwithstanding the excommunications of the popes, who supported their own canons.[300] St Louis endeavoured to bring it into
repute by the translations of Justinian's works, made according to his orders, which are still in
manuscript in our libraries; and I have already observed that they made great use of them in compiling the Institutions. Philip the Fair ordered the Laws of Justinian to be taught only as written reason in those provinces of France that were governed by customs; and they were adopted as a law in those provinces where the Roman law had been received.[301]
I have already noticed that the manner of
proceeding by
judicialcombat required very little knowledge in the judges; disputes were
decided according to the usage of each place, and to a few simple customs received by tradition. In Beaumanoir's time there were two different ways of administering justice;[302] in some places they tried by peers,[303] in others by bailiffs: in following the former way, the peers gave judgment according to the practice of their court; in the latter, it was the prud'hommes, or old men, who pointed out this same practice to the bailiffs.[304] This whole
proceeding required neither learning, capacity, nor study. But when the dark code of the Institutions made its appearance; when the Roman law was translated and taught in public schools; when a certain art of
procedure and jurisprudence began to be formed; when practitioners and
civilians were seen to rise, the peers and the prud'hommes were no longer capable of judging: the peers began to withdraw from the lords'
tribunals; and the lords were very little inclined to assemble them; especially as the new form of trial, instead of being a solemn
proceeding, agreeable to the
nobility and interesting to a
warlike people, had become a course of pleading which they neither understood, nor cared to learn. The custom of
trying by peers began to be less used;[305] that of
trying, by bailiffs to be more so; the bailiffs did not give judgment themselves,[306] they summed up the evidence and
pronounced the judgment of the prud'hommes; but the latter being no longer capable of judging, the bailiffs themselves gave judgment.
This was effected so much the easier, as they had before their eyes the practice of the ecclesiastic courts; the canon and new civil law both concurred alike to abolish the peers.
Thus fell the usage
hitherto constantly observed in the French
monarchy, that judgment should not be
pronounced by a single person, as may be seen in the Salic laws, the capitularies, and in the first law-writers under the third race.[307] The contrary abuse which obtains only in local
jurisdictions has been moderated, and in some measure redressed, by introducing in many places a judge's
deputy, whom he consults, and who represents the ancient prud'hommes by the obligation the judge is under of
taking two graduates in cases that deserve a
corporal punishment; and, in fine, it has become of no effect by the extreme facility of
appeals.
43. The same Subject continued. Thus there was no law to
prohibit the lords from
holding their courts themselves; none to abolish the functions of their peers; none to
ordain the creation of bailiffs; none to give them the power of judging. All this was effected insensibly, and by the very necessity of the thing. The knowledge of the Roman law, the decrees of the courts, the new digest of the customs, required a study of which the
nobility and
illiterate people were incapable.